Jump to content

Analytic Combinatorics/Tauberian Theorem

From Wikibooks, open books for an open world

Introduction

[edit | edit source]

'Tauberian' refers to a class of theorems with many applications. The full scope of Tauberian theorems is too large to cover here.

We prove here only a particular Tauberian theorem due originally to Hardy, Littlewood and Karamata, which is useful in analytic combinatorics.

Theorem

[edit | edit source]

Theorem from Feller.[1]

If

where the sequence is monotone (always non-decreasing or always non-increasing), and then

Proof

[edit | edit source]

Proof from Feller.[2]

  • We express our theorem in terms of a measure with a density function such that .
  • The Laplace transform of is [3]
  • By the power series expansion of , as , .
  • Therefore, as .
  • as .[4]
  • is the Laplace transform of . To express this in terms of the measure , we integrate the latter to get .
  • We use the continuity theorem to show that this implies , or (setting ) .
  • We prove that this implies .
  • Therefore, .

Measure and probability distributions

[edit | edit source]

A measure assigns a positive number to a set. It is a generalisation of concepts such as length, area or volume.

Graph of u(x) shown as a step-function in blue. There are two examples of the measure U: U(1.5) is the area under the curve in orange, U{[2.4, 2.6]} is the area under the curve in green.

In our case, our measure is the area under the curve of the step function that takes the values of our coefficients, . Therefore, . If is an integer, . We define to be the area under the curve confined to the interval . If the interval is contained in the interval for some and is the length of , then .

A measure can be converted to a probability distribution with density , assigning a probability to how likely a random variable will take on a value less than or equal to . We do this because probability distributions have two properties which we make use of in our proof.

We define to be the probability that a random variable will take on a value in the set .

Property 1: Expectation or mean

[edit | edit source]

The expectation or mean of a probability distribution with density is calculated as .

We also define .

Theorem 1
Let be a sequence of probability distributions with expectations , if then for .[5]
Proof
Assume . Let be a continuous function such that for all . Let A be an interval such that , and therefore, for the complement , for sufficiently large.
Because is continuous it is possible to partition into intervals so small that oscillates by less than .
We can then estimate in by a step function which assumes constant values within each and such that for all . We define for , so that for .
Therefore, .
For sufficiently large ,
Because then for sufficiently large , .
Putting it all together,
which implies .[6]

Property 2: Convergence

[edit | edit source]
Lemma 1
Let be an arbitrary sequence of points. Every sequence of numerical functions contains a subsequence that converges for all .[7]
Row 4, , (in blue) is contained in the previous 3 rows, contains all the subsequent rows and converges at . All (in green) are contained in and therefore converge for . This argument can be repeated for all .
Proof
For a sequence of functions we can find a subsequence that converges at . Out of the subsequence we find a subsequence that converges at . Continue in this way to find sequences that converge for the point , but not necessarily any of the previous points.
Construct a diagonal sequence . This sequence converges for all because all but the first terms are contained in . This is true for all .[8]
Theorem 2
Every sequence of probability distributions possesses a subsequence that converges to a probability distribution .[9]
Proof
By lemma 1, we can find a subsequence that converges for all points of a dense sequence. Denote the limit the sequence converges for each by . For that are not one of , is the greatest lower bound of all for .
is increasing between 0 and 1. If we define to be equal to at all points of continuity and if is a point of discontinuity. For a point of continuity , we can find two points such that , and .
are monotone, therefore . The limit of differs from by no more than , so as for all points of continuity.[10]
Theorem 3
If then the limit of every subsequence equals .[11]
Proof
By the definition of limits, for . Therefore, for any subsequence , when .[12]

Laplace transform

[edit | edit source]

The Laplace Transform can be seen as the continuous analogue of the power series, where becomes . is replaced by because it is easier to integrate.

We define the Laplace transform of a probability distribution as .

If has the density then we can also define the Laplace tranform of as .[13]

If our density is zero for , we can also see that the Laplace transform is equivalent to the expectation .[14]

Theorem 4
Distinct probability distributions have distinct Laplace transforms.[15]

Continuity theorem

[edit | edit source]
Theorem 5
Let be a sequence of probability distributions with Laplace transforms , then implies .[16]
Proof
Because the Laplace transforms are equivalent to expectations, we can use theorem 1 with to prove that implies .
By theorem 2, if is a subsequence that converges to , then the Laplace transforms of converge to the Laplace transform of .
By assumption in the theorem, the Laplace transforms converge to , then by theorem 3 all its subsequences also converge to so that .
Because Laplace transforms are unique, . But this will be true for every subsequence so by theorem 3 .[17]

This proof can be extended more generally to measure by defining our probability distribution in terms of the measure , .[18]

Asymptotics of the density function

[edit | edit source]
Theorem 6
If has a monotone density and then as .[19]
Proof
For ,
.
As the right side tends to . By theorem 2, there exists a sequence such that
Therefore
which implies . This limit is independent of the chosen sequence therefore is true for any sequence. For
as .[20]

Dense

[edit | edit source]

A subset of a set is called dense if the closure of is equivalent to , i.e. . This means that if then is either in the subset or is on the boundary of that subset. If it is on the boundary then we can select elements of which are arbitrarily close to .

Notes

[edit | edit source]
  1. Feller 1971, pp. 447.
  2. Feller 1971, pp. 445-447.
  3. Evertse 2024, pp. 152.
  4. Mimica 2015, pp. 19.
  5. Feller 1971, pp. 249.
  6. Feller 1971, pp. 249-250.
  7. Feller 1971, pp. 267.
  8. Feller 1971, pp. 267.
  9. Feller 1971, pp. 267.
  10. Feller 1971, pp. 267-268.
  11. Feller 1971, pp. 267.
  12. Feller 1971, pp. 267-268.
  13. Feller 1971, pp. 431-432.
  14. Feller 1971, pp. 430.
  15. Feller 1971, pp. 430.
  16. Feller 1971, pp. 431.
  17. Feller 1971, pp. 431.
  18. Feller 1971, pp. 433.
  19. Feller 1971, pp. 446.
  20. Feller 1971, pp. 446.

References

[edit | edit source]
  • Evertse, Jan-Hendrik (2024). Analytic Number Theory (Mastermath) Part I: Prime Number Theory. Chapter 5: Tauberian theorems (PDF).
  • Feller, William (1971). An Introduction to Probability Theory and Its Applications. Volume II (2nd ed.). John Wiley & Sons.
  • Mimica, Ante (2015). Laplace Transform (PDF).