The following theory was originally developed by world chess champion Emmanuel Lasker in his 1905 paper "Zur theorie der Moduln und Ideale" ("On the theory of modules and ideals") on polynomial rings, and then generalised by Emmy Noether to commutative rings satisfying the ascending chain condition (noetherian rings), in her revolutionary 1921 paper "Idealtheorie in Ringbereichen".
Definition 19.4:
An ideal is called primary ideal if and only if the following holds:
- .
Clearly, every prime ideal is primary.
We have the following characterisations:
Theorem 19.5 (characterisations of primary ideals):
Let , with denoting the radical ideal of . The following are equivalent:
- is primary.
- If , then either or or .
- Every zerodivisor of is nilpotent.
Proof 1:
1. 2.: Let be primary. Assume and neither nor . Since , for a suitable . Since and , for a suitable .
2. 3.: Let be a zerodivisor of , that is, for a certain such that . Hence , that is, for a suitable .
3. 1.: Let . Then either or or is a zerodivisor within , which is why for a suitable .
Proof 2:
1. 3.: Let be primary, and let be a zerodivisor within . Then for a and hence for a suitable .
3. 2.: Let . Assume neither nor . Then both and are zerodivisors in , and hence are nilpotent, which is why for suitable and hence .
2. 1.: Let . Assume not and not . Then in particular , that is, for suitable .
Theorem 19.6:
If is any primary ideal, then is prime.
Proof:
Let . Then for a suitable . Hence either and thus or for a suitable and hence .
Following the exposition of Zariski, Samuel and Cohen, we deduce the classical Noetherian existence theorem from two lemmas and a definition.
Definition 19.7:
An ideal is called irreducible if and only if it can not be written as the intersection of finitely many proper superideals.
Lemma 19.8:
In a Noetherian ring, every irreducible ideal is primary.
Proof:
Assume there exists an irreducible ideal which is not primary. Since is not primary, there exist such that , but neither nor for any . We form the ascending chain of ideals
- ;
this chain is ascending because . Since we are in a Noetherian ring, this chain eventually stabilizes at some ; that is, for we have . We now claim that
- .
Indeed, is obvious, and for we note that if , then
for suitable and , which is why , hence , since thus , , hence and . Therefore .
Furthermore, by the choice of and both and are proper superideals, contradicting the irreducibility of .
Lemma 19.9:
In a Noetherian ring, every ideal can be written as the finite intersection of irreducible ideals.
Proof:
Assume otherwise. Consider the set of all ideals that are not the finite intersection of irreducible ideals. If we are given an ascending chain within that set
- ,
this chain has an upper bound, since it stabilizes as we are in a Noetherian ring. We may hence choose a maximal element among all ideals that are not the finite intersection of irreducible ideals. itself is thus not irreducible. Hence, it can be written as the intersection of strict superideals; that is
for appropriate . Since is maximal, each is a finite intersection of irreducible ideals, and hence so is , which contradicts the choice of .
Corollary 19.10:
In a Noetherian ring, every ideal can be written as the finite intersection of primary ideals.
Proof:
Combine lemmas 19.8 and 19.9.
In fact, once we have a primary composition for a given ideal, we can find a minimal primary decomposition of that ideal. But before we prove that, we need a general fact about radicals first.
Lemma 19.12:
Let be ideals. Then
- .
One could phrase this lemma as "radical interchanges with finite intersections".
Proof:
:
:
Let . For each , choose such that . Set
- .
Then , hence .
Note that for infinite intersections, the lemma need not (!!!) be true.
Theorem 19.13:
Let be an ideal in a ring that has a primary decomposition. Then also has a minimal primary decomposition.
Proof 1:
First of all, we may exclude all primary ideals for which
- ;
the intersection won't change if we do that, for intersecting with a superset changes nothing in general.
Then assume we are given a decomposition
- ,
and for a fixed prime ideal set
- ;
due to theorem 19.6,
- .
We claim that is primary, and . For the first claim, note that by the previous lemma
- .
For the second claim, let . If there is nothing to prove. Otherwise let . Then there exists such that , and hence for a suitable . Thus , and hence for all and suitable . Pick
- .
Then . Hence, is primary.
In general, we don't have uniqueness for primary decompositions, but still, any two primary decompositions of the same ideal in a ring look somewhat similar. The classical first and second uniqueness theorems uncover some of these similarities.
Proof:
We begin by deducing an equation. According to theorem 19.2 and lemma 19.12,
- .
Now we fix and distinguish a few cases.
- If , then obviously .
- If (where again ), then if we must have since no power of is contained within .
- If , but , we have , since
In conclusion, we find
- .
Assume first that is prime. Then the prime avoidance lemma implies that is contained within one of the , , and since , .
Let now for be given. Since the given primary decomposition is minimal, we find such that , but . In this case, by the above equation.
This theorem motivates and enables the following definition:
Definition 19.15:
Let be any ideal that has a minimal primary decomposition
- .
Then the ideals are called the prime ideals belonging to .
We now prove two lemmas, each of which will below yield a proof of the second uniqueness theorem (see below).
Lemma 19.16:
Let be an ideal which has a primary decomposition
- ,
and let again for all . If we define
- ,
then is an ideal of and .
Proof:
Let . There exists such that without , and a similar with an analogous property in regard to . Hence , but not since is prime. Also, . Hence, we have an ideal.
Let . There exists such that
- .
In particular, . Since no power of is in , .
Lemma 19.17:
Let be multiplicatively closed, and let
be the canonical morphism. Let be a decomposable ideal, that is
for primary , and number the such that the first have empty intersection with , and the others nonempty intersection. Then
- .
Proof:
We have
by theorem 9.?. If now , lemma 9.? yields . Hence,
- .
Application of on both sides yields
- ,
and
since holds for general maps, and means , where and ; thus , that is . This means that
- .
Hence , and since no power of is in ( is multiplicatively closed and ), .
Note that applied to reduced sets consisting of only one prime ideal, this means that if all prime subideals of a prime ideal belonging to also belong to , then the corresponding is predetermined.
Proof 1 (using lemma 19.16):
We first reduce the theorem down to the case where is the set of all prime subideals belonging to of a prime ideal that belongs to . Let be any reduced system. For each maximal element of that set (w.r.t. inclusion) define to be the set of all ideals in contained in . Since is finite,
- ;
this need not be a disjoint union (note that these are not maximal ideals!). Hence
- .
Hence, let be an ideal belonging to and let be an isolated system of subideals of . Let be all the primary ideals belonging to not in . For those ideals, we have , and hence we find . For each take large enough so that . Then
- ,
which is why
.
From this follows that
- ,
where is the element in the primary decomposition of to which is associated, since clearly for each element of the left hand side, and thus , but also . But on the other hand, implies . Hence for any such lemma 19.16 implies
- ,
which in turn implies
- .
Proof 2 (using lemma 19.17):
Let be an isolated system of prime ideals belonging to . Pick
- ,
which is multiplicatively closed since it's the intersection of multiplicatively closed subsets. The primary ideals of the decomposition of which correspond to the are precisely those having empty intersection with , since any other primary ideal in the decomposition of must contain an element outside all , since otherwise its radical would be one of them by isolatedness. Hence, lemma 19.17 gives
and we have independence of the particular decomposition.
The following are useful further theorems on primary decomposition.
First of all, we give a proposition on general prime ideals.
Proof:
Since the product is contained in the intersection, it suffices to prove the theorem under the assumption that .
Indeed, assume none of the is contained in . Choose for . Since is prime, . But it's in the product, contradiction.
This proposition has far-reaching consequences for primary decomposition, given in Corollary 19.22. But first, we need a lemma.
Lemma 19.21:
Let be a primary ideal, and assume is prime such that . Then .
Proof:
If , then .
Proof:
The first assertion follows from proposition 19.20 and lemma 19.21. The second assertion follows since any prime ideal belonging to contains .