This Quantum World/Appendix/Relativity/Lorentz
The case against
[edit | edit source]In a hypothetical world with we can define (a universal constant with the dimension of a velocity), and we can cast into the form
If we plug in then instead of the Galilean we have Worse, if we plug in we obtain : if object travels with speed relative to and if travels with speed relative to (in the same direction), then travels with an infinite speed relative to ! And if travels with relative to and travels with relative to 's speed relative to is negative:
If we use units in which then the invariant proper time associated with an infinitesimal path segment is related to the segment's inertial components via
This is the 4-dimensional version of the 3-scalar which is invariant under rotations in space. Hence if is positive, the transformations between inertial systems are rotations in spacetime. I guess you now see why in this hypothetical world the composition of two positive speeds can be a negative speed.
Let us confirm this conclusion by deriving the composition theorem (for ) from the assumption that the and axes are rotated relative to the and axes.
The speed of an object following the dotted line is relative to the speed of relative to is and the speed of relative to is Invoking the trigonometric relation
we conclude that Solving for we obtain
How can we rule out the a priori possibility that ? As shown in the body of the book, the stability of matter — to be precise, the existence of stable objects that (i) have spatial extent (they "occupy" space) and (ii) are composed of a finite number of objects that lack spatial extent (they don't "occupy" space) — rests on the existence of relative positions that are (a) more or less fuzzy and (b) independent of time. Such relative positions are described by probability distributions that are (a) inhomogeneous in space and (b) homogeneous in time. Their objective existence thus requires an objective difference between spactime's temporal dimension and its spatial dimensions. This rules out the possibility that
How? If and if we use natural units, in which we have that
As far as physics is concerned, the difference between the positive sign in front of and the negative signs in front of and is the only objective difference between time and the spatial dimensions of spacetime. If were positive, not even this difference would exist.
The case against zero K
[edit | edit source]And what argues against the possibility that ?
Recall the propagator for a free and stable particle:
If were to vanish, we would have There would be no difference between inertial time and proper time, and every spacetime path leading from to would contribute the same amplitude to the propagator which would be hopelessly divergent as a result. Worse, would be independent of the distance between and To obtain well-defined, finite probabilities, cancellations ("destructive interference") must occur, and this rules out that
The actual Lorentz transformations
[edit | edit source]In the real world, therefore, the Lorentz transformations take the form
Let's explore them diagrammatically, using natural units (). Setting we have This tells us that the slope of the axis relative to the undashed frame is Setting we have This tells us that the slope of the axis is The dashed axes are thus rotated by the same angle in opposite directions; if the axis is rotated clockwise relative to the axis, then the axis is rotated counterclockwise relative to the axis.
We arrive at the same conclusion if we think about the synchronization of clocks in motion. Consider three clocks (1,2,3) that travel with the same speed relative to To synchronize them, we must send signals from one clock to another. What kind of signals? If we want our synchronization procedure to be independent of the language we use (that is, independent of the reference frame), then we must use signals that travel with the invariant speed
Here is how it's done:
Light signals are sent from clock 2 (event ) and are reflected by clocks 1 and 3 (events and respectively). The distances between the clocks are adjusted so that the reflected signals arrive simultaneously at clock 2 (event ). This ensures that the distance between clocks 1 and 2 equals the distance between clocks 2 and 3, regardless of the inertial frame in which they are compared. In where the clocks are at rest, the signals from have traveled equal distances when they reach the first and the third clock, respectively. Since they also have traveled with the same speed they have traveled for equal times. Therefore the clocks must be synchronized so that and are simultaneous. We may use the worldline of clock 1 as the axis and the straight line through and as the axis. It is readily seen that the three angles in the above diagram are equal. From this and the fact that the slope of the signal from to equals 1 (given that ), the equality of the two angles follows.
Simultaneity thus depends on the language — the inertial frame — that we use to describe a physical situation. If two events are simultaneous in one frame, then there are frames in which happens after as well as frames in which hapens before
Where do we place the unit points on the space and time axes? The unit point of the time axis of has the coordinates and satisfies as we gather from the version of (\ref{ds2}). The unit point of the axis has the coordinates and satisfies The loci of the unit points of the space and time axes are the hyperbolas that are defined by these equations: